Karl
The Dao Bums-
Content count
6,656 -
Joined
-
Last visited
-
Days Won
25
Everything posted by Karl
-
After consideration I decided it was easier just to use Ayn Rand's own essay on the subject. Here it is in full: The Objectivist Ethics by Ayn Rand Paper delivered by Ayn Rand at the University of Wisconsin Symposium on âEthics in Our Timeâ in Madison, Wisconsin, on February 9, 1961. Since I am to speak on the Objectivist Ethics, I shall begin by quoting its best representativeâJohn Galt, in Atlas Shrugged: âThrough centuries of scourges and disasters, brought about by your code of morality, you have cried that your code had been broken, that the scourges were punishment for breaking it, that men were too weak and too selfish to spill all the blood it required. You damned man, you damned existence, you damned this earth, but never dared to question your code. . . . You went on crying that your code was noble, but human nature was not good enough to practice it. And no one rose to ask the question: Good?âby what standard? âYou wanted to know John Galtâs identity. I am the man who has asked that question. âYes, this is an age of moral crisis. . . . Your moral code has reached its climax, the blind alley at the end of its course. And if you wish to go on living, what you now need is not to return to morality . . . but to discover it.â What is morality, or ethics? It is a code of values to guide manâs choices and actionsâthe choices and actions that determine the purpose and the course of his life. Ethics, as a science, deals with discovering and defining such a code. The first question that has to be answered, as a precondition of any attempt to define, to judge or to accept any specific system of ethics, is: Why does man need a code of values? Let me stress this. The first question is not: What particular code of values should man accept? The first question is: Does man need values at allâand why? Is the concept of value, of âgood or evilâ an arbitrary human invention, unrelated to, underived from and unsupported by any facts of realityâor is it based on a metaphysical fact, on an unalterable condition of manâs existence? (I use the word âmetaphysicalâ to mean: that which pertains to reality, to the nature of things, to existence.) Does an arbitrary human convention, a mere custom, decree that man must guide his actions by a set of principlesâor is there a fact of reality that demands it? Is ethics the province of whims: of personal emotions, social edicts and mystic revelationsâor is it the province of reason? Is ethics a subjective luxuryâor an objective necessity? In the sorry record of the history of mankindâs ethicsâwith a few rare, and unsuccessful, exceptionsâmoralists have regarded ethics as the province of whims, that is: of the irrational. Some of them did so explicitly, by intentionâothers implicitly, by default. A âwhimâ is a desire experienced by a person who does not know and does not care to discover its cause. No philosopher has given a rational, objectively demonstrable, scientific answer to the question of why man needs a code of values. So long as that question remained unanswered, no rational, scientific, objective code of ethics could be discovered or defined. The greatest of all philosophers, Aristotle, did not regard ethics as an exact science; he based his ethical system on observations of what the noble and wise men of his time chose to do, leaving unanswered the questions of: why they chose to do it and why he evaluated them as noble and wise. Most philosophers took the existence of ethics for granted, as the given, as a historical fact, and were not concerned with discovering its metaphysical cause or objective validation. Many of them attempted to break the traditional monopoly of mysticism in the field of ethics and, allegedly, to define a rational, scientific, nonreligious morality. But their attempts consisted of trying to justify them on social grounds, merely substituting society for God. The avowed mystics held the arbitrary, unaccountable âwill of Godâ as the standard of the good and as the validation of their ethics. The neomystics replaced it with âthe good of society,â thus collapsing into the circularity of a definition such as âthe standard of the good is that which is good for society.â This meant, in logicâand, today, in worldwide practiceâthat âsocietyâ stands above any principles of ethics, since it is the source, standard and criterion of ethics, since âthe goodâ is whatever it wills, whatever it happens to assert as its own welfare and pleasure. This meant that âsocietyâ may do anything it pleases, since âthe goodâ is whatever it chooses to do because it chooses to do it. Andâsince there is no such entity as âsociety,â since society is only a number of individual menâthis meant that some men (the majority or any gang that claims to be its spokesman) are ethically entitled to pursue any whims (or any atrocities) they desire to pursue, while other men are ethically obliged to spend their lives in the service of that gangâs desires. This could hardly be called rational, yet most philosophers have now decided to declare that reason has failed, that ethics is outside the power of reason, that no rational ethics can ever be defined, and that in the field of ethicsâin the choice of his values, of his actions, of his pursuits, of his lifeâs goalsâman must be guided by something other than reason. By what? Faithâinstinctâintuitionârevelationâfeelingâtasteâurgeâwishâwhim. Today, as in the past, most philosophers agree that the ultimate standard of ethics is whim (they call it âarbitrary postulateâ or âsubjective choiceâ or âemotional commitmentâ)-and the battle is only over the question of whose whim: oneâs own or societyâs or the dictatorâs or Godâs. Whatever else they may disagree about, todayâs moralists agree that ethics is a subjective issue and that the three things barred from its field are: reasonâmindâreality. If you wonder why the world is now collapsing to a lower and ever lower rung of hell, this is the reason. If you want to save civilization, it is this premise of modern ethicsâand of all ethical historyâthat you must challenge. To challenge the basic premise of any discipline, one must begin at the beginning. In ethics, one must begin by asking: What are values? Why does man need them? âValueâ is that which one acts to gain and/or keep. The concept âvalueâ is not a primary; it presupposes an answer to the question: of value to whom and for what? It presupposes an entity capable of acting to achieve a goal in the face of an alternative. Where no alternative exists, no goals and no values are possible. I quote from Galtâs speech: âThere is only one fundamental alternative in the universe: existence or nonexistenceâand it pertains to a single class of entities: to living organisms. The existence of inanimate matter is unconditional, the existence of life is not: it depends on a specific course of action. Matter is indestructible, it changes its forms, but it cannot cease to exist. It is only a living organism that faces a constant alternative: the issue of life or death. Life is a process of self-sustaining and self-generated action. If an organism fails in that action, it dies; its chemical elements remain, but its life goes out of existence. It is only the concept of âLifeâ that makes the concept of âValueâ possible. It is only to a living entity that things can be good or evil.â To make this point fully clear, try to imagine an immortal, indestructible robot, an entity which moves and acts, but which cannot be affected by anything, which cannot be changed in any respect, which cannot be damaged, injured or destroyed. Such an entity would not be able to have any values; it would have nothing to gain or to lose; it could not regard anything as for or against it, as serving or threatening its welfare, as fulfilling or frustrating its interests. It could have no interests and no goals. Only a living entity can have goals or can originate them. And it is only a living organism that has the capacity for self-generated, goal-directed action. On the physical level, the functions of all living organisms, from the simplest to the most complexâfrom the nutritive function in the single cell of an amoeba to the blood circulation in the body of a manâare actions generated by the organism itself and directed to a single goal: the maintenance of the organismâs life.1 An organismâs life depends on two factors: the material or fuel which it needs from the outside, from its physical background, and the action of its own body, the action of using that fuel properly. What standard determines what is proper in this context? The standard is the organismâs life, or: that which is required for the organismâs survival. No choice is open to an organism in this issue: that which is required for its survival is determined by its nature, by the kind of entity it is. Many variations, many forms of adaptation to its background are possible to an organism, including the possibility of existing for a while in a crippled, disabled or diseased condition, but the fundamental alternative of its existence remains the same: if an organism fails in the basic functions required by its natureâif an amoebaâs protoplasm stops assimilating food, or if a manâs heart stops beatingâthe organism dies. In a fundamental sense, stillness is the antithesis of life. Life can be kept in existence only by a constant process of self-sustaining action. The goal of that action, the ultimate value which, to be kept, must be gained through its every moment, is the organismâs life. An ultimate value is that final goal or end to which all lesser goals are the meansâand it sets the standard by which all lesser goals are evaluated. An organismâs life is its standard of value: that which furthers its life is the good, that which threatens it is the evil. Without an ultimate goal or end, there can be no lesser goals or means: a series of means going off into an infinite progression toward a nonexistent end is a metaphysical and epistemological impossibility. It is only an ultimate goal, an end in itself, that makes the existence of values possible. Metaphysically, life is the only phenomenon that is an end in itself: a value gained and kept by a constant process of action. Epistemologically, the concept of âvalueâ is genetically dependent upon and derived from the antecedent concept of âlife.â To speak of âvalueâ as apart from âlifeâ is worse than a contradiction in terms. âIt is only the concept of âLifeâ that makes the concept of âValueâ possible.â In answer to those philosophers who claim that no relation can be established between ultimate ends or values and the facts of reality, let me stress that the fact that living entities exist and function necessitates the existence of values and of an ultimate value which for any given living entity is its own life. Thus the validation of value judgments is to be achieved by reference to the facts of reality. The fact that a living entity is, determines what it ought to do. So much for the issue of the relation between âisâ and âought.â Now in what manner does a human being discover the concept of âvalueâ? By what means does he first become aware of the issue of âgood or evilâ in its simplest form? By means of the physical sensations of pleasure or pain. Just as sensations are the first step of the development of a human consciousness in the realm of cognition, so they are its first step in the realm of evaluation. The capacity to experience pleasure or pain is innate in a manâs body; it is part of his nature, part of the kind of entity he is. He has no choice about it, and he has no choice about the standard that determines what will make him experience the physical sensation of pleasure or of pain. What is that standard? His life. The pleasure-pain mechanism in the body of manâand in the bodies of all the living organisms that possess the faculty of consciousnessâserves as an automatic guardian of the organismâs life. The physical sensation of pleasure is a signal indicating that the organism is pursuing the right course of action. The physical sensation of pain is a warning signal of danger, indicating that the organism is pursuing the wrong course of action, that something is impairing the proper function of its body, which requires action to correct it. The best illustration of this can be seen in the rare, freak cases of children who are born without the capacity to experience physical pain; such children do not survive for long; they have no means of discovering what can injure them, no warning signals, and thus a minor cut can develop into a deadly infection, or a major illness can remain undetected until it is too late to fight it. Consciousnessâfor those living organisms which possess itâis the basic means of survival. The simpler organisms, such as plants, can survive by means of their automatic physical functions. The higher organisms, such as animals and man, cannot: their needs are more complex and the range of their actions is wider. The physical functions of their bodies can perform automatically only the task of using fuel, but cannot obtain that fuel. To obtain it, the higher organisms need the faculty of consciousness. A plant can obtain its food from the soil in which it grows. An animal has to hunt for it. Man has to produce it. A plant has no choice of action; the goals it pursues are automatic and innate, determined by its nature. Nourishment, water, sunlight are the values its nature has set it to seek. Its life is the standard of value directing its actions. There are alternatives in the conditions it encounters in its physical backgroundâsuch as heat or frost, drought or floodâand there are certain actions which it is able to perform to combat adverse conditions, such as the ability of some plants to grow and crawl from under a rock to reach the sunlight. But whatever the conditions, there is no alternative in a plantâs function: it acts automatically to further its life, it cannot act for its own destruction. The range of actions required for the survival of the higher organisms is wider: it is proportionate to the range of their consciousness. The lower of the conscious species possess only the faculty of sensation, which is sufficient to direct their actions and provide for their needs. A sensation is produced by the automatic reaction of a sense organ to a stimulus from the outside world; it lasts for the duration of the immediate moment, as long as the stimulus lasts and no longer. Sensations are an automatic response, an automatic form of knowledge, which a consciousness can neither seek nor evade. An organism that possesses only the faculty of sensation is guided by the pleasure-pain mechanism of its body, that is: by an automatic knowledge and an automatic code of values. Its life is the standard of value directing its actions. Within the range of action possible to it, it acts automatically to further its life and cannot act for its own destruction. The higher organisms possess a much more potent form of consciousness: they possess the faculty of retaining sensations, which is the faculty of perception. A âperceptionâ is a group of sensations automatically retained and integrated by the brain of a living organism, which gives it the ability to be aware, not of single stimuli, but of entities, of things. An animal is guided, not merely by immediate sensations, but by percepts. Its actions are not single, discrete responses to single, separate stimuli, but are directed by an integrated awareness of the perceptual reality confronting it. It is able to grasp the perceptual concretes immediately present and it is able to form automatic perceptual associations, but it can go no further. It is able to learn certain skills to deal with specific situations, such as hunting or hiding, which the parents of the higher animals teach their young. But an animal has no choice in the knowledge and the skills that it acquires; it can only repeat them generation after generation. And an animal has no choice in the standard of value directing its actions: its senses provide it with an automatic code of values, an automatic knowledge of what is good for it or evil, what benefits or endangers its life. An animal has no power to extend its knowledge or to evade it. In situations for which its knowledge is inadequate, it perishesâas, for instance, an animal that stands paralyzed on the track of a railroad in the path of a speeding train. But so long as it lives, an animal acts on its knowledge, with automatic safety and no power of choice: it cannot suspend its own consciousnessâit cannot choose not to perceiveâit cannot evade its own perceptionsâit cannot ignore its own good, it cannot decide to choose the evil and act as its own destroyer. Man has no automatic code of survival. He has no automatic course of action, no automatic set of values. His senses do not tell him automatically what is good for him or evil, what will benefit his life or endanger it, what goals he should pursue and what means will achieve them, what values his life depends on, what course of action it requires. His own consciousness has to discover the answers to all these questionsâbut his consciousness will not function automatically. Man, the highest living species on this earthâthe being whose consciousness has a limitless capacity for gaining knowledgeâman is the only living entity born without any guarantee of remaining conscious at all. Manâs particular distinction from all other living species is the fact that his consciousness is volitional. Just as the automatic values directing the functions of a plantâs body are sufficient for its survival, but are not sufficient for an animalâsâso the automatic values provided by the sensory-perceptual mechanism of its consciousness are sufficient to guide an animal, but are not sufficient for man. Manâs actions and survival require the guidance of conceptual values derived from conceptual knowledge. But conceptual knowledge cannot be acquired automatically. A âconceptâ is a mental integration of two or more perceptual concretes, which are isolated by a process of abstraction and united by means of a specific definition. Every word of manâs language, with the exception of proper names, denotes a concept, an abstraction that stands for an unlimited number of concretes of a specific kind. It is by organizing his perceptual material into concepts, and his concepts into wider and still wider concepts that man is able to grasp and retain, to identify and integrate an unlimited amount of knowledge, a knowledge extending beyond the immediate perceptions of any given, immediate moment. Manâs sense organs function automatically; manâs brain integrates his sense data into percepts automatically; but the process of integrating percepts into conceptsâthe process of abstraction and of concept-formationâis not automatic. The process of concept-formation does not consist merely of grasping a few simple abstractions, such as âchair,â âtable,â âhot,â âcold,â and of learning to speak. It consists of a method of using oneâs consciousness, best designated by the term âconceptualizing.â It is not a passive state of registering random impressions. It is an actively sustained process of identifying oneâs impressions in conceptual terms, of integrating every event and every observation into a conceptual context, of grasping relationships, differences, similarities in oneâs perceptual material and of abstracting them into new concepts, of drawing inferences, of making deductions, of reaching conclusions, of asking new questions and discovering new answers and expanding oneâs knowledge into an ever-growing sum. The faculty that directs this process, the faculty that works by means of concepts, is: reason. The process is thinking. Reason is the faculty that identifies and integrates the material provided by manâs senses. It is a faculty that man has to exercise by choice. Thinking is not an automatic function. In any hour and issue of his life, man is free to think or to evade that effort. Thinking requires a state of full, focused awareness. The act of focusing oneâs consciousness is volitional. Man can focus his mind to a full, active, purposefully directed awareness of realityâor he can unfocus it and let himself drift in a semiconscious daze, merely reacting to any chance stimulus of the immediate moment, at the mercy of his undirected sensory-perceptual mechanism and of any random, associational connections it might happen to make. When man unfocuses his mind, he may be said to be conscious in a subhuman sense of the word, since he experiences sensations and perceptions. But in the sense of the word applicable to manâin the sense of a consciousness which is aware of reality and able to deal with it, a consciousness able to direct the actions and provide for the survival of a human beingâan unfocused mind is not conscious. Psychologically, the choice âto think or notâ is the choice âto focus or not.â Existentially, the choice âto focus or notâ is the choice âto be conscious or not.â Metaphysically, the choice âto be conscious or notâ is the choice of life or death. Consciousnessâfor those living organisms which possess itâis the basic means of survival. For man, the basic means of survival is reason. Man cannot survive, as animals do, by the guidance of mere percepts. A sensation of hunger will tell him that he needs food (if he has learned to identify it as âhungerâ), but it will not tell him how to obtain his food and it will not tell him what food is good for him or poisonous. He cannot provide for his simplest physical needs without a process of thought. He needs a process of thought to discover how to plant and grow his food or how to make weapons for hunting. His percepts might lead him to a cave, if one is availableâbut to build the simplest shelter, he needs a process of thought. No percepts and no âinstinctsâ will tell him how to light a fire, how to weave cloth, how to forge tools, how to make a wheel, how to make an airplane, how to perform an appendectomy, how to produce an electric light bulb or an electronic tube or a cyclotron or a box of matches. Yet his life depends on such knowledgeâand only a volitional act of his consciousness, a process of thought, can provide it. But manâs responsibility goes still further: a process of thought is not automatic nor âinstinctiveâ nor involuntaryânor infallible. Man has to initiate it, to sustain it and to bear responsibility for its results. He has to discover how to tell what is true or false and how to correct his own errors; he has to discover how to validate his concepts, his conclusions, his knowledge; he has to discover the rules of thought, the laws of logic, to direct his thinking. Nature gives him no automatic guarantee of the efficacy of his mental effort. Nothing is given to man on earth except a potential and the material on which to actualize it. The potential is a superlative machine: his consciousness; but it is a machine without a spark plug, a machine of which his own will has to be the spark plug, the self-starter and the driver; he has to discover how to use it and he has to keep it in constant action. The material is the whole of the universe, with no limits set to the knowledge he can acquire and to the enjoyment of life he can achieve. But everything he needs or desires has to be learned, discovered and produced by himâby his own choice, by his own effort, by his own mind. A being who does not know automatically what is true or false, cannot know automatically what is right or wrong, what is good for him or evil. Yet he needs that knowledge in order to live. He is not exempt from the laws of reality, he is a specific organism of a specific nature that requires specific actions to sustain his life. He cannot achieve his survival by arbitrary means nor by random motions nor by blind urges nor by chance nor by whim. That which his survival requires is set by his nature and is not open to his choice. What is open to his choice is only whether he will discover it or not, whether he will choose the right goals and values or not. He is free to make the wrong choice, but not free to succeed with it. He is free to evade reality, he is free to unfocus his mind and stumble blindly down any road he pleases, but not free to avoid the abyss he refuses to see. Knowledge, for any conscious organism, is the means of survival; to a living consciousness, every âisâ implies an âought.â Man is free to choose not to be conscious, but not free to escape the penalty of unconsciousness: destruction. Man is the only living species that has the power to act as his own destroyerâand that is the way he has acted through most of his history. What, then, are the right goals for man to pursue? What are the values his survival requires? That is the question to be answered by the science of ethics. And this, ladies and gentlemen, is why man needs a code of ethics. Now you can assess the meaning of the doctrines which tell you that ethics is the province of the irrational, that reason cannot guide manâs life, that his goals and values should be chosen by vote or by whimâthat ethics has nothing to do with reality, with existence, with oneâs practical actions and concernsâor that the goal of ethics is beyond the grave, that the dead need ethics, not the living. Ethics is not a mystic fantasyânor a social conventionânor a dispensable, subjective luxury, to be switched or discarded in any emergency. Ethics is an objective, metaphysical necessity of manâs survivalânot by the grace of the supernatural nor of your neighbors nor of your whims, but by the grace of reality and the nature of life. I quote from Galtâs speech: âMan has been called a rational being, but rationality is a matter of choiceâand the alternative his nature offers him is: rational being or suicidal animal. Man has to be manâby choice; he has to hold his life as a valueâby choice; he has to learn to sustain itâby choice; he has to discover the values it requires and practice his virtuesâby choice. A code of values accepted by choice is a code of morality.â The standard of value of the Objectivist ethicsâthe standard by which one judges what is good or evilâis manâs life, or: that which is required for manâs survival qua man. Since reason is manâs basic means of survival, that which is proper to the life of a rational being is the good; that which negates, opposes or destroys it is the evil. Since everything man needs has to be discovered by his own mind and produced by his own effort, the two essentials of the method of survival proper to a rational being are: thinking and productive work. If some men do not choose to think, but survive by imitating and repeating, like trained animals, the routine of sounds and motions they learned from others, never making an effort to understand their own work, it still remains true that their survival is made possible only by those who did choose to think and to discover the motions they are repeating. The survival of such mental parasites depends on blind chance; their unfocused minds are unable to know whom to imitate, whose motions it is safe to follow. They are the men who march into the abyss, trailing after any destroyer who promises them to assume the responsibility they evade: the responsibility of being conscious. If some men attempt to survive by means of brute force or fraud, by looting, robbing, cheating or enslaving the men who produce, it still remains true that their survival is made possible only by their victims, only by the men who choose to think and to produce the goods which they, the looters, are seizing. Such looters are parasites incapable of survival, who exist by destroying those who are capable, those who are pursuing a course of action proper to man. The men who attempt to survive, not by means of reason, but by means of force, are attempting to survive by the method of animals. But just as animals would not be able to survive by attempting the method of plants, by rejecting locomotion and waiting for the soil to feed themâso men cannot survive by attempting the method of animals, by rejecting reason and counting on productive men to serve as their prey. Such looters may achieve their goals for the range of a moment, at the price of destruction: the destruction of their victims and their own. As evidence, I offer you any criminal or any dictatorship. Man cannot survive, like an animal, by acting on the range of the moment. An animalâs life consists of a series of separate cycles, repeated over and over again, such as the cycle of breeding its young, or of storing food for the winter; an animalâs consciousness cannot integrate its entire lifespan; it can carry just so far, then the animal has to begin the cycle all over again, with no connection to the past. Manâs life is a continuous whole: for good or evil, every day, year and decade of his life holds the sum of all the days behind him. He can alter his choices, he is free to change the direction of his course, he is even free, in many cases, to atone for the consequences of his pastâbut he is not free to escape them, nor to live his life with impunity on the range of the moment, like an animal, a playboy or a thug. If he is to succeed at the task of survival, if his actions are not to be aimed at his own destruction, man has to choose his course, his goals, his values in the context and terms of a lifetime. No sensations, percepts, urges or âinstinctsâ can do it; only a mind can. Such is the meaning of the definition: that which is required for manâs survival qua man. It does not mean a momentary or a merely physical survival. It does not mean the momentary physical survival of a mindless brute, waiting for another brute to crush his skull. It does not mean the momentary physical survival of a crawling aggregate of muscles who is willing to accept any terms, obey any thug and surrender any values, for the sake of what is known as âsurvival at any price,â which may or may not last a week or a year. âManâs survival qua manâ means the terms, methods, conditions and goals required for the survival of a rational being through the whole of his lifespanâin all those aspects of existence which are open to his choice. Man cannot survive as anything but man. He can abandon his means of survival, his mind, he can turn himself into a subhuman creature and he can turn his life into a brief span of agonyâjust as his body can exist for a while in the process of disintegration by disease. But he cannot succeed, as a subhuman, in achieving anything but the subhumanâas the ugly horror of the antirational periods of mankindâs history can demonstrate. Man has to be man by choiceâand it is the task of ethics to teach him how to live like man. The Objectivist ethics holds manâs life as the standard of valueâand his own life as the ethical purpose of every individual man. The difference between âstandardâ and âpurposeâ in this context is as follows: a âstandardâ is an abstract principle that serves as a measurement or gauge to guide a manâs choices in the achievement of a concrete, specific purpose. âThat which is required for the survival of man qua manâ is an abstract principle that applies to every individual man. The task of applying this principle to a concrete, specific purposeâthe purpose of living a life proper to a rational beingâbelongs to every individual man, and the life he has to live is his own. Man must choose his actions, values and goals by the standard of that which is proper to manâin order to achieve, maintain, fulfill and enjoy that ultimate value, that end in itself, which is his own life. Value is that which one acts to gain and/or keepâvirtue is the act by which one gains and/or keeps it. The three cardinal values of the Objectivist ethicsâthe three values which, together, are the means to and the realization of oneâs ultimate value, oneâs own lifeâare: Reason, Purpose, Self-Esteem, with their three corresponding virtues: Rationality, Productiveness, Pride. Productive work is the central purpose of a rational manâs life, the central value that integrates and determines the hierarchy of all his other values. Reason is the source, the precondition of his productive workâpride is the result. Rationality is manâs basic virtue, the source of all his other virtues. Manâs basic vice, the source of all his evils, is the act of unfocusing his mind, the suspension of his consciousness, which is not blindness, but the refusal to see, not ignorance, but the refusal to know. Irrationality is the rejection of manâs means of survival and, therefore, a commitment to a course of blind destruction; that which is anti-mind, is anti-life. The virtue of Rationality means the recognition and acceptance of reason as oneâs only source of knowledge, oneâs only judge of values and oneâs only guide to action. It means oneâs total commitment to a state of full, conscious awareness, to the maintenance of a full mental focus in all issues, in all choices, in all of oneâs waking hours. It means a commitment to the fullest perception of reality within oneâs power and to the constant, active expansion of oneâs perception, i.e., of oneâs knowledge. It means a commitment to the reality of oneâs own existence, i.e., to the principle that all of oneâs goals, values and actions take place in reality and, therefore, that one must never place any value or consideration whatsoever above oneâs perception of reality. It means a commitment to the principle that all of oneâs convictions, values, goals, desires and actions must be based on, derived from, chosen and validated by a process of thoughtâas precise and scrupulous a process of thought, directed by as ruthlessly strict an application of logic, as oneâs fullest capacity permits. It means oneâs acceptance of the responsibility of forming oneâs own judgments and of living by the work of oneâs own mind (which is the virtue of Independence). It means that one must never sacrifice oneâs convictions to the opinions or wishes of others (which is the virtue of Integrity)-that one must never attempt to fake reality in any manner (which is the virtue of Honesty)-that one must never seek or grant the unearned and undeserved, neither in matter nor in spirit (which is the virtue of Justice). It means that one must never desire effects without causes, and that one must never enact a cause without assuming full responsibility for its effectsâthat one must never act like a zombie, i.e., without knowing oneâs own purposes and motivesâthat one must never make any decisions, form any convictions or seek any values out of context, i.e., apart from or against the total, integrated sum of oneâs knowledgeâand, above all, that one must never seek to get away with contradictions. It means the rejection of any form of mysticism, i.e., any claim to some nonsensory, nonrational, nondefinable, supernatural source of knowledge. It means a commitment to reason, not in sporadic fits or on selected issues or in special emergencies, but as a permanent way of life. The virtue of Productiveness is the recognition of the fact that productive work is the process by which manâs mind sustains his life, the process that sets man free of the necessity to adjust himself to his background, as all animals do, and gives him the power to adjust his background to himself. Productive work is the road of manâs unlimited achievement and calls upon the highest attributes of his character: his creative ability, his ambitiousness, his self-assertiveness, his refusal to bear uncontested disasters, his dedication to the goal of reshaping the earth in the image of his values. âProductive workâ does not mean the unfocused performance of the motions of some job. It means the consciously chosen pursuit of a productive career, in any line of rational endeavor, great or modest, on any level of ability. It is not the degree of a manâs ability nor the scale of his work that is ethically relevant here, but the fullest and most purposeful use of his mind. The virtue of Pride is the recognition of the fact âthat as man must produce the physical values he needs to sustain his life, so he must acquire the values of character that make his life worth sustainingâthat as man is a being of self-made wealth, so he is a being of self-made soul.â (Atlas Shrugged.) The virtue of Pride can best be described by the term: âmoral ambitiousness.â It means that one must earn the right to hold oneself as oneâs own highest value by achieving oneâs own moral perfectionâwhich one achieves by never accepting any code of irrational virtues impossible to practice and by never failing to practice the virtues one knows to be rationalâby never accepting an unearned guilt and never earning any, or, if one has earned it, never leaving it uncorrectedâby never resigning oneself passively to any flaws in oneâs characterâby never placing any concern, wish, fear or mood of the moment above the reality of oneâs own self-esteem. And, above all, it means oneâs rejection of the role of a sacrificial animal, the rejection of any doctrine that preaches self-immolation as a moral virtue or duty. The basic social principle of the Objectivist ethics is that just as life is an end in itself, so every living human being is an end in himself, not the means to the ends or the welfare of othersâand, therefore, that man must live for his own sake, neither sacrificing himself to others nor sacrificing others to himself. To live for his own sake means that the achievement of his own happiness is manâs highest moral purpose. In psychological terms, the issue of manâs survival does not confront his consciousness as an issue of âlife or death,â but as an issue of âhappiness or suffering.â Happiness is the successful state of life, suffering is the warning signal of failure, of death. Just as the pleasure-pain mechanism of manâs body is an automatic indicator of his bodyâs welfare or injury, a barometer of its basic alternative, life or deathâso the emotional mechanism of manâs consciousness is geared to perform the same function, as a barometer that registers the same alternative by means of two basic emotions: joy or suffering. Emotions are the automatic results of manâs value judgments integrated by his subconscious; emotions are estimates of that which furthers manâs values or threatens them, that which is for him or against himâlightning calculators giving him the sum of his profit or loss. But while the standard of value operating the physical pleasure-pain mechanism of manâs body is automatic and innate, determined by the nature of his bodyâthe standard of value operating his emotional mechanism, is not. Since man has no automatic knowledge, he can have no automatic values; since he has no innate ideas, he can have no innate value judgments. Man is born with an emotional mechanism, just as he is born with a cognitive mechanism; but, at birth, both are âtabula rasa.â It is manâs cognitive faculty, his mind, that determines the content of both. Manâs emotional mechanism is like an electronic computer, which his mind has to programâand the programming consists of the values his mind chooses. But since the work of manâs mind is not automatic, his values, like all his premises, are the product either of his thinking or of his evasions: man chooses his values by a conscious process of thoughtâor accepts them by default, by subconscious associations, on faith, on someoneâs authority, by some form of social osmosis or blind imitation. Emotions are produced by manâs premises, held consciously or subconsciously, explicitly or implicitly. Man has no choice about his capacity to feel that something is good for him or evil, but what he will consider good or evil, what will give him joy or pain, what he will love or hate, desire or fear, depends on his standard of value. If he chooses irrational values, he switches his emotional mechanism from the role of his guardian to the role of his destroyer. The irrational is the impossible; it is that which contradicts the facts of reality; facts cannot be altered by a wish, but they can destroy the wisher. If a man desires and pursues contradictionsâif he wants to have his cake and eat it, tooâhe disintegrates his consciousness; he turns his inner life into a civil war of blind forces engaged in dark, incoherent, pointless, meaningless conflicts (which, incidentally, is the inner state of most people today). Happiness is that state of consciousness which proceeds from the achievement of oneâs values. If a man values productive work, his happiness is the measure of his success in the service of his life. But if a man values destruction, like a sadistâor self-torture, like a masochistâor life beyond the grave, like a mysticâor mindless âkicks,â like the driver of a hotrod carâhis alleged happiness is the measure of his success in the service of his own destruction. It must be added that the emotional state of all those irrationalists cannot be properly designated as happiness or even as pleasure: it is merely a momentâs relief from their chronic state of terror. Neither life nor happiness can be achieved by the pursuit of irrational whims. Just as man is free to attempt to survive by any random means, as a parasite, a moocher or a looter, but not free to succeed at it beyond the range of the momentâso he is free to seek his happiness in any irrational fraud, any whim, any delusion, any mindless escape from reality, but not free to succeed at it beyond the range of the moment nor to escape the consequences. I quote from Galtâs speech: âHappiness is a state of non-contradictory joyâa joy without penalty or guilt, a joy that does not clash with any of your values and does not work for your own destruction. . . . Happiness is possible only to a rational man, the man who desires nothing but rational goals, seeks nothing but rational values and finds his joy in nothing but rational actions.â The maintenance of life and the pursuit of happiness are not two separate issues. To hold oneâs own life as oneâs ultimate value, and oneâs own happiness as oneâs highest purpose are two aspects of the same achievement. Existentially, the activity of pursuing rational goals is the activity of maintaining oneâs life; psychologically, its result, reward and concomitant is an emotional state of happiness. It is by experiencing happiness that one lives oneâs life, in any hour, year or the whole of it. And when one experiences the kind of pure happiness that is an end in itselfâthe kind that makes one think: âThis is worth living forââwhat one is greeting and affirming in emotional terms is the metaphysical fact that life is an end in itself. But the relationship of cause to effect cannot be reversed. It is only by accepting âmanâs lifeâ as oneâs primary and by pursuing the rational values it requires that one can achieve happinessânot by taking âhappinessâ as some undefined, irreducible primary and then attempting to live by its guidance. If you achieve that which is the good by a rational standard of value, it will necessarily make you happy; but that which makes you happy, by some undefined emotional standard, is not necessarily the good. To take âwhatever makes one happyâ as a guide to action means: to be guided by nothing but oneâs emotional whims. Emotions are not tools of cognition; to be guided by whimsâby desires whose source, nature and meaning one does not knowâis to turn oneself into a blind robot, operated by unknowable demons (by oneâs stale evasions), a robot knocking its stagnant brains out against the walls of reality which it refuses to see. This is the fallacy inherent in hedonismâin any variant of ethical hedonism, personal or social, individual or collective. âHappinessâ can properly be the purpose of ethics, but not the standard. The task of ethics is to define manâs proper code of values and thus to give him the means of achieving happiness. To declare, as the ethical hedonists do, that âthe proper value is whatever gives you pleasureâ is to declare that âthe proper value is whatever you happen to valueââwhich is an act of intellectual and philosophical abdication, an act which merely proclaims the futility of ethics and invites all men to play it deuces wild. The philosophers who attempted to devise an allegedly rational code of ethics gave mankind nothing but a choice of whims: the âselfishâ pursuit of oneâs own whims (such as the ethics of Nietzsche)âor âselflessâ service to the whims of others (such as the ethics of Bentham, Mill, Comte and of all social hedonists, whether they allowed man to include his own whims among the millions of others or advised him to turn himself into a totally selfless âshmooâ that seeks to be eaten by others). When a âdesire,â regardless of its nature or cause, is taken as an ethical primary, and the gratification of any and all desires is taken as an ethical goal (such as âthe greatest happiness of the greatest numberâ)âmen have no choice but to hate, fear and fight one another, because their desires and their interests will necessarily clash. If âdesireâ is the ethical standard, then one manâs desire to produce and another manâs desire to rob him have equal ethical validity; one manâs desire to be free and another manâs desire to enslave him have equal ethical validity; one manâs desire to be loved and admired for his virtues and another manâs desire for undeserved love and unearned admiration have equal ethical validity. And if the frustration of any desire constitutes a sacrifice, then a man who owns an automobile and is robbed of it, is being sacrificed, but so is the man who wants or âaspires toâ an automobile which the owner refuses to give himâand these two âsacrificesâ have equal ethical status. If so, then manâs only choice is to rob or be robbed, to destroy or be destroyed, to sacrifice others to any desire of his own or to sacrifice himself to any desire of others; then manâs only ethical alternative is to be a sadist or a masochist. The moral cannibalism of all hedonist and altruist doctrines lies in the premise that the happiness of one man necessitates the injury of another. Today, most people hold this premise as an absolute not to be questioned. And when one speaks of manâs right to exist for his own sake, for his own rational self-interest, most people assume automatically that this means his right to sacrifice others. Such an assumption is a confession of their own belief that to injure, enslave, rob or murder others is in manâs self-interestâwhich he must selflessly renounce. The idea that manâs self-interest can be served only by a non-sacrificial relationship with others has never occurred to those humanitarian apostles of unselfishness, who proclaim their desire to achieve the brotherhood of men. And it will not occur to them, or to anyone, so long as the concept ârationalâ is omitted from the context of âvalues,â âdesires,â âself-interestâ and ethics. The Objectivist ethics proudly advocates and upholds rational selfishnessâwhich means: the values required for manâs survival qua manâwhich means: the values required for human survivalânot the values produced by the desires, the emotions, the âaspirations,â the feelings, the whims or the needs of irrational brutes, who have never outgrown the primordial practice of human sacrifices, have never discovered an industrial society and can conceive of no self-interest but that of grabbing the loot of the moment. The Objectivist ethics holds that human good does not require human sacrifices and cannot be achieved by the sacrifice of anyone to anyone. It holds that the rational interests of men do not clashâthat there is no conflict of interests among men who do not desire the unearned, who do not make sacrifices nor accept them, who deal with one another as traders, giving value for value. The principle of trade is the only rational ethical principle for all human relationships, personal and social, private and public, spiritual and material. It is the principle of justice. A trader is a man who earns what he gets and does not give or take the undeserved. He does not treat men as masters or slaves, but as independent equals. He deals with men by means of a free, voluntary, unforced, uncoerced exchangeâan exchange which benefits both parties by their own independent judgment. A trader does not expect to be paid for his defaults, only for his achievements. He does not switch to others the burden of his failures, and he does not mortgage his life into bondage to the failures of others. In spiritual issuesâ(by âspiritualâ I mean: âpertaining to manâs consciousnessâ)âthe currency or medium of exchange is different, but the principle is the same. Love, friendship, respect, admiration are the emotional response of one man to the virtues of another, the spiritual payment given in exchange for the personal, selfish pleasure which one man derives from the virtues of another manâs character. Only a brute or an altruist would claim that the appreciation of another personâs virtues is an act of selflessness, that as far as oneâs own selfish interest and pleasure are concerned, it makes no difference whether one deals with a genius or a fool, whether one meets a hero or a thug, whether one marries an ideal woman or a slut. In spiritual issues, a trader is a man who does not seek to be loved for his weaknesses or flaws, only for his virtues, and who does not grant his love to the weaknesses or the flaws of others, only to their virtues. To love is to value. Only a rationally selfish man, a man of self-esteem, is capable of loveâbecause he is the only man capable of holding firm, consistent, uncompromising, unbetrayed values. The man who does not value himself, cannot value anything or anyone. It is only on the basis of rational selfishnessâon the basis of justiceâthat men can be fit to live together in a free, peaceful, prosperous, benevolent, rational society. Can man derive any personal benefit from living in a human society? Yesâif it is a human society. The two great values to be gained from social existence are: knowledge and trade. Man is the only species that can transmit and expand his store of knowledge from generation to generation; the knowledge potentially available to man is greater than any one man could begin to acquire in his own lifespan; every man gains an incalculable benefit from the knowledge discovered by others. The second great benefit is the division of labor: it enables a man to devote his effort to a particular field of work and to trade with others who specialize in other fields. This form of cooperation allows all men who take part in it to achieve a greater knowledge, skill and productive return on their effort than they could achieve if each had to produce everything he needs, on a desert island or on a self-sustaining farm. But these very benefits indicate, delimit and define what kind of men can be of value to one another and in what kind of society: only rational, productive, independent men in a rational, productive, free society. Parasites, moochers, looters, brutes and thugs can be of no value to a human beingânor can he gain any benefit from living in a society geared to their needs, demands and protection, a society that treats him as a sacrificial animal and penalizes him for his virtues in order to reward them for their vices, which means: a society based on the ethics of altruism. No society can be of value to manâs life if the price is the surrender of his right to his life. The basic political principle of the Objectivist ethics is: no man may initiate the use of physical force against others. No manâor group or society or governmentâhas the right to assume the role of a criminal and initiate the use of physical compulsion against any man. Men have the right to use physical force only in retaliation and only against those who initiate its use. The ethical principle involved is simple and clear-cut: it is the difference between murder and self-defense. A holdup man seeks to gain a value, wealth, by killing his victim; the victim does not grow richer by killing a holdup man. The principle is: no man may obtain any values from others by resorting to physical force. The only proper, moral purpose of a government is to protect manâs rights, which means: to protect him from physical violenceâto protect his right to his own life, to his own liberty, to his own property and to the pursuit of his own happiness. Without property rights, no other rights are possible. I will not attempt, in a brief lecture, to discuss the political theory of Objectivism. Those who are interested will find it presented in full detail in Atlas Shrugged. I will say only that every political system is based on and derived from a theory of ethicsâand that the Objectivist ethics is the moral base needed by that politico-economic system which, today, is being destroyed all over the world, destroyed precisely for lack of a moral, philosophical defense and validation: the original American system, Capitalism. If it perishes, it will perish by default, undiscovered and unidentified: no other subject has ever been hidden by so many distortions, misconceptions and misrepresentations. Today, few people know what capitalism is, how it works and what was its actual history. When I say âcapitalism,â I mean a full, pure, uncontrolled, unregulated laissez-faire capitalismâwith a separation of state and economics, in the same way and for the same reasons as the separation of state and church. A pure system of capitalism has never yet existed, not even in America; various degrees of government control had been undercutting and distorting it from the start. Capitalism is not the system of the past; it is the system of the futureâif mankind is to have a future. For those who are interested in the history and the psychological causes of the philosophersâ treason against capitalism, I will mention that I discuss them in the title essay of my book For the New Intellectual. The present discussion has to be confined to the subject of ethics. I have presented the barest essentials of my system, but they are sufficient to indicate in what manner the Objectivist ethics is the morality of lifeâas against the three major schools of ethical theory, the mystic, the social, the subjective, which have brought the world to its present state and which represent the morality of death. These three schools differ only in their method of approach, not in their content. In content, they are merely variants of altruism, the ethical theory which regards man as a sacrificial animal, which holds that man has no right to exist for his own sake, that service to others is the only justification of his existence, and that self-sacrifice is his highest moral duty, virtue and value. The differences occur only over the question of who is to be sacrificed to whom. Altruism holds death as its ultimate goal and standard of valueâand it is logical that renunciation, resignation, self-denial, and every other form of suffering, including self-destruction, are the virtues it advocates. And, logically, these are the only things that the practitioners of altruism have achieved and are achieving now. Observe that these three schools of ethical theory are anti-life, not merely in content, but also in their method of approach. The mystic theory of ethics is explicitly based on the premise that the standard of value of manâs ethics is set beyond the grave, by the laws or requirements of another, supernatural dimension, that ethics is impossible for man to practice, that it is unsuited for and opposed to manâs life on earth, and that man must take the blame for it and suffer through the whole of his earthly existence, to atone for the guilt of being unable to practice the impracticable. The Dark Ages and the Middle Ages are the existential monument to this theory of ethics. The social theory of ethics substitutes âsocietyâ for Godâand although it claims that its chief concern is life on earth, it is not the life of man, not the life of an individual, but the life of a disembodied entity, the collective, which, in relation to every individual, consists of everybody except himself. As far as the individual is concerned, his ethical duty is to be the selfless, voiceless, rightless slave of any need, claim or demand asserted by others. The motto âdog eat dogââwhich is not applicable to capitalism nor to dogsâis applicable to the social theory of ethics. The existential monuments to this theory are Nazi Germany and Soviet Russia. The subjectivist theory of ethics is, strictly speaking, not a theory, but a negation of ethics. And more: it is a negation of reality, a negation not merely of manâs existence, but of all existence. Only the concept of a fluid, plastic, indeterminate, Heraclitean universe could permit anyone to think or to preach that man needs no objective principles of actionâthat reality gives him a blank check on valuesâthat anything he cares to pick as the good or the evil, will doâthat a manâs whim is a valid moral standard, and that the only question is how to get away with it. The existential monument to this theory is the present state of our culture. It is not menâs immorality that is responsible for the collapse now threatening to destroy the civilized world, but the kind of moralities men have been asked to practice. The responsibility belongs to the philosophers of altruism. They have no cause to be shocked by the spectacle of their own success, and no right to damn human nature: men have obeyed them and have brought their moral ideals into full reality. It is philosophy that sets menâs goals and determines their course; it is only philosophy that can save them now. Today, the world is facing a choice: if civilization is to survive, it is the altruist morality that men have to reject. I will close with the words of John Galt, which I address, as he did, to all the moralists of altruism, past or present: âYou have been using fear as your weapon and have been bringing death to man as his punishment for rejecting your morality. We offer him life as his reward for accepting ours.â 1 When applied to physical phenomena, such as the automatic functions of an organism, the term âgoal-directedâ is not to be taken to mean âpurposiveâ (a concept applicable only to the actions of a consciousness) and is not to imply the existence of any teleological principle operating in insentient nature. I use the term âgoal-directed,â in this context, to designate the fact that the automatic functions of living organisms are actions whose nature is such that they result in the preservation of an organismâs life. âŠ
-
Except you aren't content or you wouldn't be wanting others to be anything other than what they are. You wouldn't think capitalism, ethics, morality were low forms of virtue either. This is one of the first lessons in accepting self as self. There is no way to circumvent the self in the form of being a 'contented discontent'. It is pretending to be something you are not. You can either choose to remain ignorant, become an evader, or use reason to become a moral man. You are correct to say that 'society is beyond saving' but there is no society, there are individuals of which you are one. It is therefore the ONLY thing you can do is act as an individual. You are infact acting for self, you are being consciously selfish. That's a good start, but only if you acknowledge it. What brings people to enlightenment is the realisation that they are and must act from the position of the rational self, the question then becomes-what should I do ? What principles should I live by ? (Which is the science of ethics). Capitalism, values and morals aren't a panacea, they are just concepts until grounded in reality and defined by reality. Capitalism as defined by the state is not capitalism at all-this is deliberate evasion or ignorance, as is the Marxian definition. Our minds are are ONLY tools of survival. In order to survive we must apply reason. Coercive Force is the antithesis of reason, the antithesis of the mind and therefore the antithesis of survival and life. However, drifting, acting deliberately ignorant, failing to apply reason properly, evading or surrendering the mind is an invitation for those who are prepared to use force to win. By not acting from the position of rational selfishness the good dies and evil survives. Now, if you are evading, or perhaps you are innocently ignorant of the truth, then you are unaware that you have left open the gate and a Tiger is eating your food and mauling your loved ones.
-
That's all we have. Just as you are reasoning now. You can only do so if you are an existent, independent consciously aware entity. Without a spirit there would be no 'you' and no way of reasoning. Existence comes before consciousness and consciousness comes before reason/logic. Consciousness awareness grows as the ability to reason becomes stronger and more reliable integrations are made. Bad reasoning shrinks conscious awareness. We often refer to people in the state of total irrationality as withdrawn. They become tied up in mind clutter from disintegrated concepts which produces a mnd that grinds away without managing to integrate much at all. Conscious awareness closes down.
-
There is no way to apply reason if there is no spirit. Some apply reason and create disintegration or floating concepts, they create errors, but they still require spirit. Spirit being the conscious awareness of existence.
-
Spirit is an integral part of reason and logic.
-
Does the media largely exaggerate how much "terror" there is going on in the world?
Karl replied to Taoway's topic in The Rabbit Hole
Yes, that's it, it's the same with the political situation. It's no good making something illegal, or installing yet another political party because the problem we face cannot ever be solved pragmatically. It's just a bad philosophy, like a bad program on a computer, it doesn't matter how the inputs are altered, the outputs will almost always be in error. -
The guy I was talking to mentioned WW2 and said the British paratroopers who landed in occupied France were fed a cocktail of drugs. He was in one of the drops and remembers landing next to one of his platoon who had both legs shot away and was still attempting to run on the remaining stumps. It's said that the Nazi high command were all on drugs of one sort or another and it was these drugs that allowed them to take decisions without any feelings of concern.
-
What's your take on it now ? I knew a guy who had been living on Cocaine and heroin as a barrister for a long time before he ended up in prison. He told me many stories about users and how it was reasonably common amongst judges, doctors and politicians. I asked him if he thought legalising it was the best option- he got really angry. He told me that none of the drugs should be legalised and especially not methadone (describing it as one of the most addictive drugs to be offered to addicts). You know it was the CIA that imported a mass of LSD from Switzerland and kicked off the whole hippy, trippy, drug thing.
-
Does the media largely exaggerate how much "terror" there is going on in the world?
Karl replied to Taoway's topic in The Rabbit Hole
You were saying that your present philosophy is one which has got you through bad times and so you are loath to mess with it. You said you liked the clear thought that takes its base in my philosophy but that you felt more secure staying with what has worked. I was saying that if you did decide to look at other philosophies such as Tao, Objectivism etc, then that would happen when it was ready to happen and not before-thus the fruit falls from the tree only when ripe. -
Nope cannabis users develop a tolerance to some of the effects (coordination, sedative) and not others. You can't get any higher than a certain point no matter how much you have, but, here's the kicker, you can get higher by reducing the amount taken. Cannabis isn't like other drugs. I wasn't been hyperbolic. The jury is out on the ALL because most of them were, had been taking substances such as alcohol, steroids and others. It's enough to ask the question at least. It isn't true that all cannabis uses are chilled out and relaxed. That's the impression given, but I know from personal experience that this is not true. I've seen it effect people in a similar way to LSD, they become very distraught, animated and angst ridden. I've wondered if the effects were similar to the Christmas mushrooms once served as treats in Northern areas-the Santa story of only 'good children' getting the presents, may have more to it. As I said, I wouldnt criminalise it. I don't believe in prohibition, but it's clear to me that more study needs to be undertaken and those that wish to partake may require something like a psyche evaluation before they begin to use and regular advisory check ups throughout the time they are taking it. I certainly don't have a perfect solution, but it would be wise to temper the usual liberal 'anything goes' approach in this case until we know more. It's always been assumed that alcohol is more dangerous because it is addictive, it does cause violence and destruction of the body, but alcohol is pretty well limited to harm of the immediate family who know what's going on and of course to the person themselves. It doesn't lead to a calculation to drive a van through a crowd of people in order to kill the maximum number, neither does it get you into a group who buy automatic weapons and go into a nightclub shooting, then torturing people by cutting off body parts and stuffing them into the victims mouths.
-
Theres thinking and then there's thinking. If the aim is to turn off drifting thoughts then it's easier to encourage the use of reason/logic to make your mind into a tool to work for you. The undisciplined mind will drift in a chaos of ungrounded conceptual churning clutter. It's like letting a dog do whatever it wants, so, the responsibility is to the owner to give the correct training and not to chain it up.
-
Yes, neither of them will win, but Johnson is showing a significantly good poll to at least suggest that future elections may be less cut and dried. The question of drug and alcohol use is a tough one. I think this requires a philosophical change rather than a legal one. Prohibition doesn't work. Neither can there be a 'war on drugs', but it is a major issue if it results in death and destruction, so those who take psychoactive drugs are, in some cases, damaging their brains to the point of causing severe paranoia and doing so is equivalent to giving a toddler dynamite and fuses to play with. Alcohol causes immediate effect, but psychoactive drugs can cause immediate changes which last a lifetime.
-
What about Gary Johnson ? Isn't he right up your street, closest to anarchist -small government, low taxes etc stein wants gun control by which she means a ban. Mind you, neither do I agree that it should be an open free for all for any kind of weapon. Both want to legalise cannabis which, I think is a mistake. I never used to take that view, but every one of these idiots that have shot up schools or public places have been taking it. I have two nieces that have developed mental illness shortly after using. I'm not saying that correlation is cause, but I think we need to think carefully before being passed off as being harmless. TCH is weird, it takes less and less of it to get high as the brain latches on to it, that means there are some alterations taking place.
-
I bet you shot him then forgot you had done so. He's probably the mulch in your rose bushes. See if there are any watches, buttons or belt buckles in the flower beds.
-
I don't know about your Green Party, but ours is effectively communism sewn inside a sack marked environmental concern. Comrades all digging with bare hands in the dirt of a communal home farm seems to be their aim. Be careful you don't vote communism in by the back door.
-
Correlation is not causality.
-
Tolerance, Apathy and the Fall of Civilizations
Karl replied to Golden Dragon Shining's topic in The Rabbit Hole
Im happy with your definition, however I'm aware of how easy it is to twist. Isn't it simpler just to call it rational selfishness ? An independent person acting in a totally rational, moral way, to obtain values through honest effort and find happiness through that route. He does not rely on others 'be neither my brothers keeper, or him mine', but trades for peaceful, voluntary, mutual benefit with others. He welcomes those things which benefits life and rejects those that don't. -
Does the media largely exaggerate how much "terror" there is going on in the world?
Karl replied to Taoway's topic in The Rabbit Hole
It will happen if it happens and no amount of watching, praying or shouting will get it to fall any faster than that. -
Not thinking is the easiest thing in the world. The hardest is coherent, logical reasoned thought at all times instead of chaotic churning.
-
So, your dilemma is either vote for an independent, or not to vote at all. I choose the latter these days if there isn't a clear alternative. I don't mean someone who I think will do a good job, but at least someone who doesn't represent the establishment status quo. A vote for anyone else but Trump or Clinton is a waste of time, but if you feel you must, then vote Garry Johnson.
-
The damning verdict on the IMF experts on themselves. The strategy relied on forlorn hopes that the "confidence fairy" would lift Greece out of this policy-induced nose-dive. âHighly optimisticâ plans to raise $50bn from privatisation sales came to little. Some assets did not even have clear legal ownership. The chronic âlack of realismâ lasted until late 2011. By then the damage was done. http://www.telegraph.co.uk/business/2016/07/28/imf-admits-disastrous-love-affair-with-euro-apologises-for-the-i/ oh dem experts are real gud. Same experts dat boss Cameroon tell us make whole heap a trouble iss we leaves, yas sir dat surely wot then done tole us Brussels slaves.
-
Does the media largely exaggerate how much "terror" there is going on in the world?
Karl replied to Taoway's topic in The Rabbit Hole
To quote a well known Buddhist phrase 'the fruit falls from the tree when it is ripe'. -
Or how he defines himself-which was the question that was asked. Many people are Christians and students. What defines you as a person. It's a very good question and revealing. Same as: where are you ? How do you know it ? What should you do. Defining oneself is a very good thought exercise.
-
Does the media largely exaggerate how much "terror" there is going on in the world?
Karl replied to Taoway's topic in The Rabbit Hole
You know it really isn't like that. I first held the view that in the way you probably did, then I held your current view for several years, but, when I moved to the Objectivist view-now I don't really know quite how to explain it, but I wasn't at all upset by the change, it was a feeling like I had come down to earth in a good way, very grounded and solid. -
But what makes you, you ? Everybody has senses and emotions, even animals.